The Pleasant Profession |
Review by |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Unbound: London, 2019 |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
480 pages | November 2019 | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
The approach to Heinlein Both the passage of decades and the changing values of the science fiction community have been less than kind to Robert Heinlein. From the start of his writing career until not long before his end, he was the writer who set the standard for his genre — one that, as Willy Ley commented, was often too high for other writers to meet. Since his death, his literary skill has been not so much denied as found irrelevant, much as Kipling's was starting in the 1930s, when then notable poets such as W.H. Auden and T.S. Eliot felt compelled to apologize for liking his work. In both cases, the issue was the author's unacceptability to the progressive ideology of the time: Kipling was charged with racism and imperialism, Heinlein with sexism, racism, and militarism. In this context, the goals of Farah Mendlesohn's The Pleasant Profession of Robert A. Heinlein will strike many Heinlein readers as a happy change. No less progressive than most other present-day critics of science fiction, Mendlesohn nonetheless is open to a more nuanced view of Heinlein. And even better, she undertakes to arrive at one through the project of reading the entirety of his fiction and examining what he actually says. She recognizes the American patriotism that endured all his life, and the libertarian sympathies of his later years, but also notes the socialist views of his earlier career, and his willingness to envision radical personal moralities at odds with the conservatism he's often identified with. She doesn't equate his ideas with those that are currently thought of as radical, but she does recognize that Heinlein's views are a form of radicalism — and one that, for the most part, she doesn't simply dismiss as wrong, even when she disagrees with it. Heinlein definitely was a socialist when he began writing science fiction, though neither a Marxist nor a technocrat, an indigenous American variant (favored by Hugo Gernsback, who created "scientifiction" as a genre). His approach to socialism was more in the spirit of the "social credit" movement that gave its name to a Canadian political party. He always remained devoted to the Constitution of the United States and especially the Bill of Rights. Mendlesohn calls attention to this aspect of Heinlein's intellectual evolution, emphasizing the pragmatism of his original movement away from belief in a planned economy and the gradualness of his shift to libertarianism. She describes Heinlein as "alienated by the shift to both identity politics and a large government state" (though it seems odd to suppose that the Democratic Party, when Heinlein was active in it in the 1930s, didn't represent "large government"). She points out, though, that "Although many of Heinlein's political opinions changed over his forty-year writing career, it is important to understand that his underlying beliefs did not." Mendlesohn also emphasizes a more contemporary version of leftist thought, seeing Heinlein as a precursor of present-day identity politics in his opposition to racism, advocacy of women's rights, and questioning of traditional ideas about "gender" or sex roles. She views much-criticized works such as Farnham's Freehold as errors of literary judgment that produce a novel that many readers will take as support for racism, not as expressions of actual racism; it's notable that in the epilogue she argues that the black American character in that novel is clearly portrayed as virtuous, indeed more so than the title character. It's also noteworthy that two of the themes she focuses on, Heinlein's consistent opposition to slavery and his emphasis on consent in sexual relationships, while clearly reflecting her own political outlook, are also entirely congruent with the libertarianism of Heinlein's later works. Her approach to Heinlein also offers insights into his characters. I was particularly struck by Mendlesohn's recognition that Friday (in the novel titled for her, Friday) has been subjected to sustained denial of her own self-respect, to the point where she can only rebel without knowing that she's doing so; and by Mendlesohn's noting as significant Edith Stone's insistence, in The Rolling Stones, on putting her duty as a doctor ahead of her role as the mother of a family. Mendlesohn explicitly views Heinlein as an experimental writer, and thus is prepared to pay close attention to his literary technique. This seems to be often underestimated by commenters who view Heinlein as a literary seat-of-the pants pilot with little self-awareness. A reading of his correspondence with Larry Niven and Jerry Pournelle about the problems of their first collaboration, The Mote in God's Eye, will dispel this illusion — and happily, Mendlesohn doesn't seem to have needed one. Unfortunately, this creditable enterprise is flawed by a long series of factual errors, to the point where I'm tempted to say that there is at least one for everything Heinlein wrote. Some are about facts of publication:
Some are simple textual errors, in which Heinlein is quoted inaccurately:
Others are errors about the events of the stories, some minor and others not:
This is a long and perhaps tedious list. But its very length shows that Mendlesohn didn't just miss one or two minor points, oversights such as can find their way into the best and most carefully checked book. She had a consistent pattern of missing them. Despite her laudable goal of basing her discussion on Heinlein's entire oeuvre, she didn't read it so closely as to get all these points right; nor, having completed her book on him, did she go back to the books she discussed and check that she had gotten everything right. Does this matter? It might seem not; these are errors on small points, after all. But it's the practice of historical scholars to insist on getting small details right — for example, to quote a source exactly, word for word and punctuation mark for punctuation mark; academic copy editors are trained not to change such details, even if they go against a publisher's style guide. Petty details are important to the scholarly enterprise. And there are at least two reasons for this. First, not all details are as petty as they appear: an incorrect publication date may give a wrong impression of a book's historical context or its place in the author's development, or a character's misstated age may alter the literary effect of a story about them. Second, if an author consistently gets details wrong, the reader's confidence in their larger conclusions is undermined. How trustworthy are Mendlesohn's larger conclusions? This isn't as straightforward a question. But I can suggest a few interpretations of Heinlein that I think unsound. In the discussions of Tunnel in the Sky, Mendlesohn describes Grant Cowper, the leader of the "coup" that takes over the stranded colony from Rod Walker, as a "waste of space." This is at best oversimplified. During the swarming of the colony by the "dopy joes," seasonally turned vicious, Cowper leads the struggle against them and in the end dies fighting to keep them out, showing what Heinlein considers the ultimate virtue of caring more for the welfare of his community than for his own survival; this is at least a redemptive scene, like the death of Sam at the climax of Starman Jones. Restored to leadership of the community, Walker names it "Cowpertown" and persuades the other residents not to leave the location, but to hold and fortify it, and at least part of his unwillingness to leave at the end seems to be resistance to letting Cowper's memory fade. And more fundamentally than that, Cowper's takeover clearly seeks to provide the colony with a survival tool that Walker doesn't understand or really know about: law and legitimacy, which transform it from a collection of individualists using engineering methods for their own personal benefit to a common enterprise — as shown by the discussion where Cowper recruits Walker to be his second-in-command. Mendlesohn tells us that Walker learns that "practical people can create tools, settlements and societies," but it's Cowper from whom he learns that final lesson, and who creates the society. She criticizes Cowper's treatment of women and especially his "sending them away from a fight," but biologically, the survival of a population depends on having enough female members to reproduce itself; males are expendable — and the lost colony is under primitive conditions where this argument applies with full force, as it doesn't back on overpopulated Earth where women such as Rod's sister can become soldiers. Heinlein uses one of his typical narrative tricks in this book, telling the story from the point of view of a character who is not its real hero, and who in fact is antagonistic to its hero and then "learns better"; and though Mendlesohn explicitly identifies this literary device in other Heinlein stories, she seems to have missed it here, even though Heinlein gives repeated pointers to it in the text of the novel. Mendlesohn takes Farnham's Freehold to be a racist work even though, first, she explicitly quotes a long passage that amounts to an argument that racial categories and attributes are socially constructed and are not based on actual evidence, which few people want; and second, she also quotes a passage where Barbara Farnham asks Hugh Farnham, "How many white men of today could be trusted with the power Ponse had and use it with as much gentleness as he did use it?" This is an explicit statement of the moral equivalence of white subordination to blacks and black subordination to whites, and one that Hugh simply accepts as valid. Mendlesohn actually accepts that Heinlein's intended meaning is not racist (and to me it seems anti-racist, in the style of a mathematical "without loss of generality" argument: if it's wrong for A to oppress and exploit B, it's equally wrong for B to oppress and exploit A), but concludes that because "most science-fiction readers" will take the novel simply as an attack on black people — and therefore it must be read as one. If so (and while many science fiction readers have taken it that way, the usual response has been to reject the putative message, not to embrace it, which would make the novel a failure as racist propaganda), it would argue that Heinlein's attempt at an anti-racist message did not get through to an audience responding to it as rhetoric (ironically, that is, it also failed as anti-racist propaganda), but not that its theme — which much be judged by the understanding of the most intelligent, sophisticated, and critical readers — is racist; if anything, it seems to be the evil effects of racism and of unequal power no matter who holds the greater power. Mendlesohn acknowledges the complexity of Heinlein's thought, but ends by reducing it to the simplicity of (some) readers' responses. (And I must note that when I read Farnham's Freehold at 14, I didn't get that racist message out of it; it seemed to me to say very clearly that racism in any form was evil.) I would also note a key purely literary point about this. In Hugh Farnham's conversation with Joe, his former servant, he protests that Joe was a well treated servant, not a slave; Joe asks if Hugh has ever traveled through Alabama as a "nigger," and adds, "Then shut up. You don't know what you are talking about." Very few characters in Heinlein's writing tell people to shut up. But one notable previous case occurs in "If This Goes On—", when John Lyle, the viewpoint character, asks, in effect, "Why don't the Jews adopt our religion? We've told them often enough that it's the true faith" just after he and his roommate Zeb have seen a mob lynching a Jew, and Zeb angrily tells him "Shut up!" The phrase comes from a figure speaking with moral authority who is angered past endurance by racism. And Mendlesohn will go on to argue that Joe does have moral authority, and indeed is a better man than Hugh; the reader is clearly intended to accept the justice of his anger toward American racism. (I discuss this in more detail in my review of Farnham's Freehold.) Given these difficulties, is The Pleasant Profession of Robert A. Heinlein worthless? Not at all! Mendlesohn's goal, to assess Heinlein's literary work as a whole, based on reading all of it, is an admirable project. Moreover, many of her insights are worthwhile; even her discussion of Farnham's Freehold, which I have found flawed, also picks up some nuances I had not seen before. But given its many small errors and occasional dubious readings, The Pleasant Profession can't be taken as an authoritative guide to its subject; the reader is well advised to check its conclusions against the actual texts before adopting them. This is an interesting book, but had its original aim been carried out with more care it might have been a magnificent one.
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
© 2019 William H. Stoddard |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
LitCrit at Troynovant Notes to a Proofreader |
ReFuture at Troynovant |
|||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
|